Postcolonial Studies, Vol 1, No 2, pp 23 254, 1998
Re-imagining land ownership in
Australia
HELEN VERRAN
A front page report in The Australian newspaper of 10 August 1994 began
Cape York pastoralists and Aborigines have jointly called for state and federal
governments to legislate ¼ a form of statutory co-existence of title on pastoral
leases. ¼ [A] marathon seven-hour meeting in the Queensland town of Coen last
week ¼ sought to address the uncertainty and ® nancial di culties ¯ owing to Cape
York pastoralists from the Wik people’s claim to a large area of Cape York,
including 12 pastoral leases.
These negotiations, begun by the Cape York Aborigines and pastoralists, and
later joined by representatives of local tourist operators, did in due course lead
to a form of agr eement between these disparate interests. However, the develop-
ing alliance was strongly opposed by the Queensland Government, which tried
assiduously, although unsuccessfully, to bring negotiations to a halt.
In 1994 t he Wik people’s claim to a large part of Cape York had every chance
of being recognised in law, and that likelihood led to the development of new
sorts of negotiating between Aborigines and pastoralists. The full bench of the
High Court of Australia delivered a si gn cant ruling relating to land ownership
in Australia in June 1992: the land of Australia and the surrounding islands had
been owned by indigenous peoples before 1770 when British o cials cl aimed
the land for the British Crown. With subsequent legislation, this meant that most
land not speci® cally claimed in the past under freehold title became eligible for
claims by indigenous comm unities under the Native Title Act 1993. A central
provision of this Act, which was formulated in the public gaze under intense
pressure from indigenous Australians, is multiple possibilities and opportunities
for negotiation between the parties involved.
Subsequently the High Court of Australia, in its Wi k decision of 23 December
1996, ruled that native title could coexist with pastoral rights on leases. This was
sign cant because it followed that native title had not been extinguished on the
mainland of Australia in pastoral areas where man y Aboriginal people live,
maintaining their traditional association with their lands. The scene was set for
the new and unfamiliar politics that were being negotiated in Coen in 1994, to
spread quickly and widely, generating fear and confusion on all sides. This in
turn prompted the (now conservative) Federal Government to introduce what has
become known as its `Wik Bill to amend the N ative Title Act. The whole thrust,
and the explicit central provision of this amendment, which on the day I write
Helen Verran is a senior lecturer in the Department of History and Philosophyof Science, University of Melbourne.
1368-8790/98/020237-18 $7.00
Ó
1998 The Institute of Postcolonial Studies 237
HELEN VERRAN
this paragraph is currently being considered for a second time by the Senate, is
the abolition of the rights of parties to negotiate.
1
The issue of the survival of Wik native title was still undecided when those
discussions reported so enthusiastically in The Australian, between a few
Aboriginal Australians and descendants of those who dispossessed them, got
under way in a small town in t he bush of far north Queensland in 19 94. But what
had become obvious by then, and is still obvious, although some would wish
things otherwise, was that it is no t only land title that the 1992 Native Title
ruling institutionally recognises. Aboriginal traditions of knowing were recog-
nised in a new way by that ruling, known n ow in Australia as the `Mabo Ruling,
celebrating one of t he leading plaintiffs. Recognising Native Title amounts to
recognising the existence, and the rationality, of knowledge systems of indige-
nous Australians. And, as evidenced by the negotiations in Coen, some non-Ab-
original Australians now have strong reasons to ® nd ways to work modern ways
of knowing (largely originating in colonising European t raditions) together with
the very different knowledge traditions of indigenous Australians. If they dont
they are likely to suffer `uncertainty and ® nancial dif® culties’ .
It is not my aim here to comment on this series of legal rulings and
parliamentary proceedings, rather I want to focus on the n egotiations over land
title now required (but perhaps soon to be outlawed) i n many parts of Australia.
Among other things, I want to ask what sorts of things land titles are, and how
they are generated within a knowledge tradition, that is, to carry out a form of
ontological investigation. I suggest that looking at some of the puzzles that
participants in negotiations over native title and pastoral leases might face can
be helpful in understanding what I see as a new form of politics emerging in
contemporary Australia. I identify this as a politics being waged over ontic and
epistemic commitments; a politics over what there is and who/what can know it.
In particular I suggest that looking at some of their puzzles allows us to see
an element inherent i n knowing which, currently, is almost entirely ignored by
modern practices and accounts of knowledge. I call this element `the imaginary’
and point to its necessary involvement in knowing an d knowledge making. I
show the imaginary as something constitutive of, and constituted by, ontic and
epistemic commitments.
2
Western philosophy has a continuing interest in `other’ knowledge traditions,
although the idea of working knowledge systems together as implied in the need
for Aboriginal Native Title, and pastoral lease holders to negotiate has not in the
past featured in that interest. Blinded by an ep istemology obsessed with scient i® c
knowledge, theory is taken to be the sole expression of true knowledge.
Philosophers (and anthropologists) puzzle over whether or not `traditional’
knowledge systems have theory, and if they do, whether or not it is rational. In
the early 1980s the topic was bogged down in a maze of debates over relativism
and realism.
3
However the topic has recently emerged rather differently both in
empirical and in speculative work in science studies, associated with a concern
for actual practices of doing science.
4
Mixing epistemologies and ontologies is
no longer an outlawed notion in so me parts of that discipline.
What has remained unnoticed and unexplored in the new focus on practice in
science studies is that many of the previously supposed limitations of other
238
RE-IMAGINING LAND OWNERSHIP IN AUSTRALIA
knowledge systems compared with science have been dissolved. Emphasising
the locatedness of all knowing and knowledge making, focuses up the `heteroge-
neous material-symbolic assemblages constituting strategies, techniques and
entities which enable the workings of all k nowledge systems.
5
The challenge
now is h ow to go beyond, the now quite common, descriptions of heterogeneity.
I suggest that part of this will be recognising that these `heterogeneous material-
symbolic assemblages’ clot in a politics waged over ontic/epistemic commit-
ments. This politics is perhaps most easily identi® ed in what are often called
`cross-cultural’ contexts, such as I am concerned with in this paper, but this
politics is certainly not con® ned to such situations. In this paper, which I
understand as a contribution in both postcolonial studies and science studies, I
show that we cannot begin to understand t his politics without paying attention
to ontic/epistemic imaginaries.
Bruno Latour identi® es the juxtaposition of science and other knowledge
traditionsÐ the `modern and the `premodern’ in his (somewhat ¯ awed) termi-
nologyÐ as utterly central in science studies. For him scienti® c ways of knowing
and knowledge making are a vast covert enterprise of `translation, which i s
hidden by an equally vast overt endeavour of `puri® cation’ , with the second
making the ® rst possible.
the word `modern’ designates two sets of entirely different pr actices ¼ The ® rst set
¼ by `translation, creates ¼ hybrids of nature and culture. The second, by
`puri® cation’ creates two distinct ontological zones: that of human beings o n the
one hand; that of non-humans on the other. [Paradoxically] the more we forbid
ourselves to conceive of hybrids, the more possible their interbreeding becomes.
6
Latour reminds us that back in seventeenth- and eighteenth-century Europe, as
modernity solid ed, particular accounts o f knowing and acting wer e developed
and promulgated as ® nal and ultimate. Usi ng the work of Shapin and Schaffer,
7
Latour shows how these accounts were built on deceit and denial, c(K)ant and
hypocrisy. They have all the knowing and acting in the world concentrated at
one `pole’ Ð reasoning h umans. The role of the non-human domain is to be the
known about and the acted upon. Individual human knower/actors were the
triumphant epistemic agents f or 200 years, but, the very triumph now leads us
to see through this framework. The work of puri® cation, the story telling that
keeps sorting things into `nature’ and `culture’, work that must be invisibly
carried on to sustain the schema, `blows out’ and becomes visible at the end of
the twentieth century, especially to those involved in social studies of science
and technology.
At the end of the introductory chapter in We Have Never Been Modern, Latour
asks `what are we going to become? Can we aspire to Enlightenment without
modernity?’. He rejects the romantic notion that we can return to the ways of the
pre-moderns who `by dev oting themselves to conceiving o f hybrids ¼ have
excluded their proliferation, suggesting a middle way, `that we are going to
have to slow down, reorient, and regulate the proliferation of monsters by
representing their existence of® cially’ .
8
In this paper I extend Latours answer,
suggesting that slowing down and reorienting, that o cially recognising all the
239
HELEN VERRAN
monstrous hybrids of which our worlds are composed, will necessitate our
identifying and engaging in a politics waged over ontic/epistemic imaginaries.
As a way to begin imagining the negotiations between Aboriginal groups and
pastoralists which are foreshadowed in the Native Title Act, and as exempl ed
in the `marathon seven-hour meeting in the Queensland town of Coen’ in far
north Queensland in early August 1994, I want to show how questions over
knowing and acting come to life around the negotiating table. They constituted
the ® rst stumbling block in the negotiations at Coen.
9
In earlier times, for colonising Europeans, th e Aborigines of Cape York were
de® nitely not part of the knowing world. In the eyes of the grandfathers and
grandmothers of those pastoralists who in 1994 sat around the table negotiating
over ways of knowing the land they both claimed, the Wik people were, in
public contexts (as distinct from private involvements of many sorts), part of
the undifferentiated black `other’ . Being `of the natural Aborigines could be
known aboutÐ studied by anthropologists. But more importantly they could be
shot and poisoned, led away in chains from their land and i mprisoned else-
whereÐ to be civilised, to become part of the social. Only when they b ecame
individuated, modern individuals, only when they stopped being Wik, could
they k now, and act as knowing agents, although that would not necessarily
prevent their being discriminated against and denied social justice.
We might like to t hink that near the end of the twentieth century this has
changed, and perhaps even point to the Native Title Bill as at testing institutional
recognition of Ab original Australians as knowers. But, in practice Ab original
knowledge systems are often understood as being at best a partial knowledge;
Aboriginal knowers are treated as ambiguously both knowers and known,
simultaneously of the social and the natural. And this will obviously form a
® rst barrier to mutual respect and understanding on which fruitful negotiations
will depend, although it is a barrier which might be d issolved b y good
intentions.
It is not so easy to dissolve a second problem which soon became evident in
Coen in 1994. The ways in which the negotiators at Coen came up against quite
different notions of who or what can act is less easy to elaborate than the ways
questions over knowledge and knowers arose. We need t o appreciate something
of the content of Aboriginal ways of knowing to appreciate this. To demonstrate
that this issue is likely to come to life when Aborigines sit down to negotiate
with pastoralists, I tell a little of the proceedings of a landrights case which was
an important precursor to the 1992 ruling on Native Title.
Some 25 years ago Milpirrum and others, Yolngu men who are all now dead,
made a High Court challenge to the Federal Government plan to develop a huge
bauxite mine and build a large mi ning town on land they understood themselves
and other members of their clans as owning. The j udgement, which went
against the Yolngu people with whom I am intimately involved,
10
was handed
down by Justice Blackburn in 1970.
In the judge’ s view, although the claimants established the existence of a
subtle and powerful knowledge system, recognisable as a system of law, by
which particular clans were linked through ident able sites both to sections of
land and to each other,
240
RE-IMAGINING LAND OWNERSHIP IN AUSTRALIA
¼ [it] did not provide for any proprietary interest i n th e clans in any part of the
areas claimed.
11
Rather,
¼ it seems easier on the evi dence, to say that the clan belongs to the land than that
the land belongs to the clan.
12
The judge was correct in identifying that quite different notions of agency are
involved in A boriginal knowledge systems. But whether he was correct in thus
concluding that the clans had no proprietary interest is quite another matter.
What did the judge consider the evidence for the land not being property of
the clans? The crux of it was the limited rights of exclusion that clans had.
The clan’ s right to exclude others is not apparent ¼ the greatest extent to which
this right can be said to exist is in the realm of ritual. But it was never sug gested
that ritual rules ever excluded members of othe r clans completely from clan
territory; the exclusi on was only from sites.
13
Justice Blackburns ruling is now all but irrelevant but the problem of agency he
ident ed r emains, p aralysing many attempts to work Western and Aboriginal
knowledge traditions together. I suggest that an important clue to how we might
solve this problem is embedded in Justice Blackburn’ s rei® cation of exclusion as
the de® ning characteristic of ownership of land. I will return to this later.
Is it beyond the pastoralists’ grasp on the issues to constr ue their corporations
as being responsible to the places where their cattle roam, pulverising the soil
with their hard-cutting hooves? How can they think of their companies as being
owned by the land? What might be the implications for their practices as
pastoralists of this understanding? This is part of what i s being negotiated over,
but like Justice Blackburn, the pastoralists must refuse the land as agent. How
and where to begin in institutionally recognising another system of knowing and
thus owning land is deeply perplexing for most p astoralists. Like the rest of us
moderns, they are suffering from an advanced case of hardening of the
categories.
For their part, entering into negotiations over l and title, Ab original peoples
might be troubled to see t hat the pastoralists do not seem to know how to go
about negotiating, knowledge, land and ownership. As most Aboriginal groups
see it, they `own the land in the strongest possible sense: the clans in question,
distributed across the area claimed, came int o being with the land i tself. The land
was made meaningful as it was peopled in a network of interconnected places.
Through these places the land owns them as they own the land. Owning the land
is owning and publicly articulating the stories t hrough which the land is
meaningful as a set of interconnected places. And in the stories are the multiple
and complex metaphors which comprise the stuff of negotiating in Aboriginal
Australia.
In contrast to the pastoralists, on the Aboriginal side generally there are far too
many who have ideas on how to negotiate. On the basis of my experience with
Yolngu people facing similar sorts of questions, I would expect to ® nd that in
beginning negotiations, a whole range of metaphors would be worked up in
discussion. These provide the possibilities for imagining new categories, and for
241
HELEN VERRAN
reworking old categories in new ways. Just which vision might eventually
prevail as an Aboriginal people’ s position is, at the beginning, usually far from
clear. As with any negotiations in Aboriginal Australia, discussions here are
likely to be tied up with the ongoing struggle for cognitive authority, waged
through pitting metaphor against metaphor. There is often heated, and overt
struggle, over whose metaphor is going to prevail. Given time, one metaphor
will carry th e day, and it will have been greatly enriched by the controversy
surrounding its being settled upon.
Aboriginal Australian peoples generally understand themselves as having a
vast repertoire by which the world can be re-imagined, and in being re-imagined
be re-made. In English this usually goes u nder the title of `the dreaming’ . I think
a more helpful name for this conceptual resource is ` the ontic/epistemic imagi-
nary’ of Aboriginal k nowledge systems. It is this i maginary, celebrated, vener-
ated and providing possibilities for rich intellectual exchange amongst all
participants in Aboriginal community life, which in part enables the eternal
struggle to reconcile the many local knowledges which constitute Aboriginal
knowledge systems. Many Aboriginal communities know how to negotiate over
ontic categories; they have the epistemic resou rces for devising a radical form
of land title acknowledging disparate ways of knowing land.
Pastoralists are likely to have trouble of a different kind. They know there are
no metaphors or images involved in public knowing of the land which un derlies
ownership. Behind ownership there are ju st the rigid facts of quantifying and
surveying the land. Various individuals might imagine and use all sorts of
metaphors in t he ways th ey represent the land, but that is the domain of art and
emotion which has no p lace in negotiations over ownership of land. Enmeshed
in their ri gid facts pastoralists have only very slender resources for imagining a
joint title.
Pastoralists, of course, see themselves, their lives and their families as
belonging to the landÐ they are country people. But this `belonging for them
can only b e a turn of phrase. T hey might admit to strong feelings un derlying
their convictions that they are the `real owners of the land, but the love and fear
that motivates their loud protestations at land rights for Aboriginal Australians
has absolutely no place in Western land titl a cold removed factual do cument
with its map of land as mythical empty space.
How might the pastoralists solve their paralysis? I am immodest enough to
consider that I have some useful suggestions. My suggestions grow out of
contemporary u nderstandings in science studies, and are strongly mediated by
nearly 10 years of learning from and working with members of the Yolngu
Aboriginal community in the Northern Territory, and before that years of
working with Yoruba teachers in Nigeria as they struggled to reconcile the
traditions of Yoruba k nowing with contemporary school life.
If I was asked to translate between pastoralists and Aboriginal groups
negotiating over land t itle, I would begin by pointing out to the pastoralists that
they need to understand that her e they are involved in a process of knowledge
making. And in this regard there are some things they can learn from Aboriginal
Australians. The making of new knowledge is understood as a highly local affair
in Aboriginal Australia. True knowledge embeds a local balance which is
242
RE-IMAGINING LAND OWNERSHIP IN AUSTRALIA
achieved in negotiation over particular issues at particular places by particular
people, yet these understandings can be mobilised from the site of origin.
14
Firstly, I would suggest, it can help pastoralists if they underst and knowledge
and knowledge making in this em bedded or performative
15
way. Secondly, the
pastoralists would need to understand that both an imaginary and a logic,
intimately meshed, ar e involved here.
But, taking these insights on board is likely to be di cult for the pastoralists.
For a start, they ® nd it dif® cult to see these negotiations as knowledge making
and not just dirty politics. Moreover, they have always lived in a world where
true knowledge has no imaginary. Modernity circumscribes its imaginary as of
aesthetic, but not ontic or epistemic in terest.
Seeing these negotiations as knowledge making is tied up with questions
about agency and knowing. There seems t o be too much agency involved here
for moderns to understand this as knowledge making. Each side has the capacity
to interrogate, to know, the other. Westerners see true knowledge arising only
out of one-sided interrogations; for them only one side can have agency in
knowledge making. Reasoning men are knowers of truth; nature can only be
known about. The pastoralists can conceive of knowledge making about Abo-
rigines, when they are part of nature and have rights only to be silent. But as
soon as Aborigines have a voice, are recognised as knowers (even if only partial
knowers), then dealing with them becomes dirty politics, not making knowledge.
Enmeshed in their modern constitution, pastoralists see no role for negotiation in
establishing t ruth.
As part of helping pastoralists learn to see these negotiations as knowledge
making, to begin to understand true knowledge as embedded and local, and to
deal with their problems over too much agency, I would focus ® rst o n the absent
imaginary in Western epistemological traditions. On this issue I argue that
asserting that our Western imaginaries do not have a role in constituting ontic
and epistemic commitments is a denial dependent on privilege. It is useful only
when the sciences hold the unmarked position of p rivilege with respect to all
other knowledges. The pastoralists’ grandmothers and grandfathers felt no need
for an imaginary to deal with the Aborigines.
Once we see through the universalist pretensions of the sciences, and recog-
nise the vi olence that lies behind these pretensions, we must admit our need for
ontic/epistemic imaginaries, or we can’ t g et anywhere in working scien ces
together with other knowledges. Doing without imaginaries, denying the pictures
and stories inherent in our knowing, is a luxury which can no longer be justi® ed,
if indeed it ever could be. I suggest that moderns need to bring back into view
our denied imaginaries so we can more easily get on with the business of
working knowledge traditions together and recognising non-human agents, as we
make knowledge and remake worlds.
Where might the pastoralists turn to try to understand why they ® nd them-
selves there at the negotiating table with so few resources? They need a picture
of the ways that the things we take for granted have been made. They need a
story of the construction of the basic categories through which land is known in
a public sen se. Where do Westerners turn if they need to get a ® x on the basic
categories of West ern life? Surely this is the role of p hilosophy in our public l ife.
243
HELEN VERRAN
In particular, I suggest that Kant
16
whose `work stands as a watershed in the
self-understanding of modernity
17
can be useful.
But can they expect to ® nd there the pictures and stories they need? Every
school girl knows that philosophy is not a story; not a pictorial description.
Philosophy declares itself as philosophy through a break with the d omain of th e
image.
18
Yet, Michele Le Dú uff, who went looking in the texts of philosophy,
and in the pages of Kant’ s books, found something different. She found what she
called `a pr operly philosophical imaginary’ Ð images thoroughly speci® c to
philosophy. Her conclusion was that
imagery has a relation to what we call `conceptualized intellectual work, or at least
that it occupies the place of theory’ s impossible ¼ imagery copes with the
problems posed by the theoretical enterprise ¼ The imagery which is present in
theoretical texts stands in a relation of solidarity with the theoretical enterprise itself
(and with its troubles) that is, in the strict sense of the phrase imagery i s at work
in these productions.
19
Because of its strident denial of its images, and because philosophy claims to be
a self-founding discipline, making recourse to myth inevitable, most or all the
images in philosophy are about philosophy itself:
Philosophy de® nes and designs its own myths m aking use of spatial and narrative
places and layouts ¼ [Spatial] images ¼ form part of the language of the
corporation ¼ which may be, just as much as certai n principles, rules and misappre-
hensions, structuring elements of the ph ilosophical position itself.
20
And we see it clearly in Kant’ s work. The metaphor of space goes right through
Kant’ s critique. I n explaining his fundamental distinction between the analytic
and the synthetic, a spatial metaphor is implicit:
In the analytic judgement we keep to the given concept and seek to extract
something from it ¼ But in synthetic judgements I have to advance beyond the
given concept, viewing as in relation to the concept something altogether different
from what was thought in it ¼
Granted then that we must advance beyond a given concept in order to compare it
synthetically with another, a third something is necessary ¼ inner sense and its a
priori form, time.
21
(emphasis added)
Fifty pages later we get the full picture
We have now not merely explored the territory of pure understanding, and carefully
surveyed every part of it, but have also measured its extent, and assigned to
everything in it its rightful place. This domain is an island enclosed by nature itself
within unalterable limits. It is the land of truthÐ enchanting name!Ð surrounded by
a wide and stormy ocean , the native home o f illusion, where many a fog bank and
many a swiftly melting iceberg give the deceptive appearance of farther shores,
deluding the adventurous seafarer ever anew with empty h opes, and engaging him
in enterprises which he can never abandon and yet is unable to carry to com-
pletion.
22
Notwithstanding the intimate role of the spatial image in his own text, Kant casts
imagery out of reason. With his island, Kant paradoxically uses a metaphor to
244
RE-IMAGINING LAND OWNERSHIP IN AUSTRALIA
outlaw metaphor. Just as Justice Blackburn some 200 years later sees exclusion
as the d ning property of land ownership, Kant sees the exclusion of the
imaginary as the de® ning property of reason.
In dealing with imagery
Kant confronts an abyss, where were he to fall into it, he would confront chaos and
uncertainty. He pulls back onto the ground of certitude. In doing so he circum-
scribes the nature and role of the imagination, espec ially its syn thesising power,
making it dependent on understanding. ¼ This has the effect, as the Critique of
Pure Reason unfolds, not only of reducing the nature of the imagination to that of
cognition, ¼ but more importantly of driving a wedge between reason and
imagination. Reason contains no creative power, only a regulative power which
gives rules and standards.
23
The island is thus the emblem of the Kantian enterprise, yet an emblem
unthinkable in the logic of the program it seeks to establish. The image of the
bleak ordered northern isle is thus at once both a precondition of the Kantian
theory, and systematically denied. What is happening here? According to Le
uff, the textual co ict is
A sign that something important and troubling is seeking utteranceÐ something
which cannot be acknowledged but is keenly cherished.
24
What is this something, that cannot be acknowledged, which generates the
prolonged metaphor of The Critique? Le Dú uff ident es it as the need to close
the question of philosophy’s role in the global project of the Great Instauration,
as Kant, following Bacon, calls it. With his metaphor Kant is both justifying
philosophy’s role in the establishment of modernity, and giving us a vivid
picture of that stat e. The metaphor of the island allows the question to be settled
by ® at. Paradoxically, metaphor establishes an epistemic regime which excludes
itself as an epistemic element.
So turning t o philosophy can be of help to pastoralists. Seeing Kants moves,
they understand som ething of the impulses behind the peculiar denied role of the
imaginary in Western philosophy. But, in contrast t o Kant and his contempo-
raries, justifying and imagining modernity is not a top priority for pastoralists in
Australia in 1998. In terms of the Native Title Act, they need reason to justify
and imagine inclusion not exclusion.
Understanding h ow the situation aro se is one thing, working out what they
might do now is another. How are they to go on? I suggest that we take Kant’ s
metaphor in full, and treat it seriously. To take it in full is to see the island and
the seas which surround it as integral to each other. To take the metaphor
seriously is to see that it is through being lived space that both the island and
the seas become meaningful. Taking the metaphor seriously makes the notion of
empty space untenable.
To get a better idea of what it means to do this I turn now to examining the
particular puzzles that confront pastoralists as they and the Aboriginal peoples
begin to talk of working their disparate ownerships into one title. Here I am
imputing to the Aboriginal peoples generally a system of knowing and owning
land of a similar g eneral form to that of the Yolngu Aboriginal people, whose
245
HELEN VERRAN
lands, located on the other side of the Gulf of Carpentaria from the Wik lands,
are securely held under freehold title granted under the 1976 NT Land Rights
Act.
25
I have developed this way of explaining the Yolngu system over the past
10 years. It is a translation Yolngu have been intimately involved in formulat-
ing.
26
In this translation both modern and Aboriginal systems of land ownership
have an identi® ab le logic through which land can be publicly known and, since
known, owned. There are various interesting and signi® cant differences in the
logics, and in the past I have spent much time elaborating these, showing how
the logics can be understood as analogous.
27
In each case the logics translate meaning invested in the land. But the f orms
of the meaningfulness (ontic commitments), and explanations of its origins
(epistemic commitments) are quite different in the two systems. It is the very
different ways that Western traditions and Aboriginal traditions t ake the land as
meaningful that interests me here. And this, it seems to me, is what pastoralists
and Aboriginal groups need to pay most attention to.
To begin with the tradition readers of this j ournal are likely to be mo st
familiar with, moderns own land through the mediation of number. Number
constitutes an ordering recursion, a logic, which translates qualities taken t o be
in the land. Area and length are the qualities conventionally used as the basis for
quantifying land, that is, publicly knowing land, and the basis for owning
particular sections of land. Qualities come to life as images, and are conceived
of in a way which echoes the str ucture of separated integers of the number
system: an in® nite extension of units (metres, hectares etc).
What I have ju st given is an explanation of our practices of quanti® cation. It
is thoroughly uncontroversial. But what about the origins and explanations of
these practices? We are quite comfortable with recognising the pattern of
tallying on our ® ngers in t he recursive pattern of number, but where d o qualities
come from? What is the origin of this inherent meaningfulness we moderns ® nd
in land?
28
In Kantian terms, the qualities we express in our practices of quanti® cation are
synthetic a priori concepts. We can put an explanation of their origins in Kantian
terms. `Advancing beyond the structure number gives us (the analytic concept),
we view it in relation to a perceptual element, and synthesise notions of qualities
as i nite extensions’. By a series of unnoticed spatial movementsÐ inclusions
and exclusionsÐwe have explained the origins of qualities and ® rmly ruled out
the mystery. Standing on the ordered island, with a quick and controlled glimpse
at the surrounding ocean, we come to enumerated qualitiesÐquantities. But
having domesticated something of the watery chaos that surrounds us, we remain
enclosed in our certainty on our regulated islan d, and keep the imaginary out at
sea.
Without bothering about any of this complicated cognitive manú uvring, we
who use qualities every day take it for granted that the landscape is somehow
`naturally’ meaningful in that it contains qualities. Yet anyone who has tried to
describe and explain qualities to small children will r ealise that they are rather
mysterious things. We tend not to admit this, preferring to hide this mysterious
making of the land, and the material world in general, as inherently meaningful.
246
RE-IMAGINING LAND OWNERSHIP IN AUSTRALIA
Through our practices of quanti® cation with their denied imaginary, we know
and own land, maintaining t he myth that k nowable space is at once ordered and
empty. An outcome of this is that all space is equivalent; a uniform grid. In
unthinkingly using Kant s denied metaphor, what we hide from ourselves is a
paradox. That it is our very practices of quanti® cation which constitute, and in
turn are constituted by, that uniform frame of empty space.
Amongst members of Aboriginal communities, knowing land and m aking
rational judgements and decisions about land are based on very different sorts of
reasoning. They have a very different way of dealing with the paradox. In their
conceptual system land exists primarily as sets of sites; there are inherent foci
in the land connected in particular ways. Through these interconnected sites,
often cal led `sacred sites in English, land is meaningful. In describing and
explaining this system in Western terms, we can identify and separ ate logic and
metaphor. We can re-present the practices in terms which are analogous to the
ways Westerners present th eir system of publicly knowing lan d. Some Yolngu
people, for example, ® nd this an odd, even o ffensive way to do things, but they
recognise that the translation can have, and has had, p articular uses.
The primary focal sit es through which land is meaningful are connected in
ways which echo the pattern of logic common to Aboriginal Australia. This is
a logic strictly analogous to the n umber-based logic of modern life, but one
which takes its pattern not from the material pattern of tallying on ® ngers, but
from the material pattern of kinship relationsÐ gurrutu for Yolngu people. This
recursive logic modelled on kin relations translates inherent meaning of the land
in just the way the logic of number translates qualities, the meanings moderns
take to be inherent in the land. But in contrast to that stance, the mystery o f the
origins of these sets of sites, the foci of meaningfulness in the land, is celebrated
in Aboriginal communities. Stories of the making of these foci abound with
metaphor.
According to these stories, there was an eternal, simultaneous making of the
people in clan groups and of meaningful foci in the land, by eternal bei ngs as
they went about th eir living: hunting, eating, defecating, urinating, having coitus,
menstruating, crying, and having babies. This is understood to have occurred i n
what is known in English as ` the dreamtime’ , Wangarr in Yolngu l anguages.
This is often taken, incorrectly, as t he far distant past, but a contrast between
time as secular and as eternal is probably a better way to explain it. Wangarr is
time of a different sort (something like eternal time) to that in which we live our
everyday lives (secular time); it is not time only of the far distant past. It is a
time which we can ® nd here and now, and will be able to continue to ® nd i n the
future. Boundaries between these different sorts of time are continually main-
tained and celebrated in Yolngu life.
Perhaps these boundaries separating different times can be understood as
analogous to Kant’ s boundaries separating different types of space: the orderable
empty island and the chaos of a northern ocean. But whereas Kants boundary
making, and our co ntinued remaking of the boundaries as we quantify, is
hurriedly passed over and denied in modern traditions of knowing land, Yolngu
boundaries are celebrated. Traversing boundaries is overt participation in public
ceremony. Yolngu openly acknowledge that it is through traf® c acro ss
247
HELEN VERRAN
boundaries between different `time spaces’ that the foci of meaning in the
lan sacred sitesÐ are maintained. The paradox inherent in m eaningfulness, in
making ontic/epistemic commitments, is acknowledged and celebrated.
The knowledge of sites and their connections is contained in a large corpus
of stories and the songs, dances and graphic designs which go along with the
ceremonial elaboration o f these stories (hence the popular English language
notion of `Aboriginal songlines’). These are performed in ceremonies w here
both the complex logic of gurrutu (the recursion of kin relations) and particular
land sites are re-presented. The words of songs which celebrate this imaginary
are not memorised. It is the general picture of the network of p laces and their
interconnections that is memorised. Thi s is a complex set of spatial i mages, a
`cognitive map
29
which can be understood as quite analogous to the modern
imaging of qualities in material objects as held in varying extents pictured as
in® nite linear extensions, which can be made analogous to the in® nitely
extending line of integers.
It is knowing `the map , which we can understand as a matrix of vectors with
each place d ned through relations of varying intensity and direction, and
coming up with metaphoric insights to express this `map’ in performing songs
and stories, that is valued as Yolngu intellectual work. There is a correct `map
which everyone knows in greater or lesser detail, and the `map’ may be
expressed in more and less elegant ways.
But this matrix of `sacred sites’ is not all there is to land ownership in
Aboriginal Australia. The ancestral beings constituted a set of particular places
as primary in engaging in particular acts: having sex, giving birth, menstruating,
hunting, eating, shitting and piddling etc, as they made their way acro ss the land.
And in a secondary way these act ions constitute the space between these places:
the blood, or the tears, or the urine, or the honey ¯ owed in a particular way, so
that ownership radiates out from sacred sites encompassing the broadlands
between. These broadlands can be used by other clans for hunting and gathering,
and for passage, by negotiation; exclusion is only from sacred sites. Apart from
this eternally justi® ed ownership, clans may also own in a secondary way
particular sites within the broadlands of other clansÐ these are known as ringgitj
by Yolngu, and likened to clan `embassies’ . Ownership of these subsidiary sites
has been constituted historically within secular ti me, they are i mportant in the
ongoing collective life of a group of Yolngu clans. Parties of clan members
camp at these sites during times of ceremony.
For Aboriginal Australians, space is primarily constituted as live or enlivened
and inevitably not all places are equivalent; space is inherently differentiated. In
ceremony this eternal constitution of the land through the living eternal ancestral
beings, is re-presented. Particular sacred sites and associated broadlands are
ritually evoked in representing the living of the ancestors: their maki ng ® re,
collecting honey, having sex etc. This differentially focused space is also
maintained in everyday activities: hunting and gathering o f particular foods at
particular places at particular times by particular people is also seen as important
in the ongoing constitution of space.
This translation or mediation divides Yolngu Aboriginal knowing and owning
of land into logic and imaginary. It can be understood as a projecting of Kant’ s
248
RE-IMAGINING LAND OWNERSHIP IN AUSTRALIA
island and its surrounding seas on to Yolngu knowing. But it is a translation
which re¯ ects back on to th at island, bringing it more clearly into view and
acceptability. It and the sea no longer need be denied. The translation throws
light in both directions.
To be able to get on with their negotiations, the Cape York pastoralists need
to recognise that collective picturing and storytelling about the land with its
possibilities for emotional ladenness and material embeddedness is an inherent
part of kn owing it and owning it; and that Western picturing is no more and no
less rational than Aboriginal ways of picturing and thus knowing and owning the
land. Picturing and stories embedding metaphors are as much a shared ontic/
epistemic resource as the rules and regularities which accompany them. That is,
as long as moderns recognise their picturing and storytelling, we moderns can
become as rational as Aborigines. My claim is that by restoring imaginaries to
modern theories of knowledge, we will rediscover the capacity to re-imagine
ourselves, and devise ways they can work with other communitiesÐ human and
non-human.
But how can we learn to celebrate rather than d eny the ontic/epistemic
imaginaries involved in modern knowledge traditions? I have been arguing for
a radical change in our ontic/epistemic constituting metaphors, and a recognition
of their place in our knowing and acting; that we must recognise Kant’ s
treacherous sea as well as the calm island, and include our use of imaginaries in
our accounts of our knowledge. We could understand this taking of our
imaginaries in full, and taking them seriously, as changing ontic/epistemic mode.
It involves a different way of dealing with the paradox inherent in on tic/epis-
temic commitment, in meaningfulness.
Representation is the current o rthodox Western ontic/epistemic mode. Knowl-
edge is a representation of various situations on Kant’ s empty ordered island.
What happens when we include the treacherous sea in what we are representing?
Straightaway we see our installation on the ordered island as an accomplishment,
an ontic act. And we continue to enact our i nstallation o f this ordered island
again and again, not least in our practices of quant cation. In beginning is an
act, and it is as much an act by the island as it is by those whose practices (for
example practices of quant cation) become possible in and through the act. It
is a co-constitution of island and those who order them selves with quant cation.
Or to put it in an Aboriginal way, the people and the land come into being
together, and thus are deeply implicated in and by each other. The inherent
uncertainty, messiness and multiplicity of action is what Kant effectively hid.
Including the sea h as us more like Aborigines, the performative or enacting
mode emerges as epistemically primary. Representational knowledge comes to
be understood as a secondary, derived form. Taking Kant’ s imaginary of an
ordered (that is enlivened) isl and seriously, amounts to an epistemic commitment
to knowledge as enacted rather than as propositional.
I want now to explore what might follow from such a shift in ontic/epistemic
mode, using land titles as my example. In doing this I will suggest a basis on
which pastoralists might go into fruitful negotiations with Aboriginal people
developing agreement over working native title an d pastoral leases together. I
suggest that we could understand such n egotiations as constituting a politics of
249
HELEN VERRAN
ontic/epistemic commitments. My main purpose here is to show how we might
use our ontic/epistemic imaginaries in such a politics.
Switching from underst anding land titles as texts which neutrally represent
both lan with a map, and the testimony as to ownershi with legal words,
and beginning to think of land titles as working in the performative mode would
involve at least two shifts. First, we would need to recognise the performative
nature of the testimony element in titles. We have hidden the fact that the written
components of land titles are no less and no more than test imony backed up by
an elaborate set of `technologies’Ð social, material and literar land surveys
and grid making, t itles of® ces, a vast enterprise which continually underpins the
performance of testimony over land titles.
30
The second element is to recognise that maps perform particular places in the
land. Land is not empty space and maps are not mere representations. Land is
lumpy, bumpy lived material place, and maps perform this place. Maps ar e a
particular way of living space and encode a complex set of conventions and
standards that only hold because they co ntinue to be enacted as people make and
use maps, and because a great deal of work is put into making them hold.
31
Kant’ s denied island has had us hiding from ourselves the conventions
inherent in land titles, and the work which maintains them, just as much as it
hides the imaginary implicit in representing the land in maps. In engaging a
performative epistemic mode, we more easily recognise both these, and land
titles become evident as messy, complex material-symbolic assemblages in part
held together as working entities by an imaginary: a vision of t he categories
through which land is inherently meaningful (ontic commitments) and an
account of the origins of this meaningfulness (epistemic commitments).
32
We
enact these ontic and epistemic commitments in ownership, calling on the shared
imaginary in doing so.
The ways moderns have treated imaginaries in the pas using and denying
themÐ has enabled us to make (and deny) the translations by which we
constitute complex hybrids such as land titles. The imaginaries have enabled the
titlesÐheterogeneous material-symbolic assemblagesÐ to be active in making
and remaking our world. And denying the imaginaries has enabled us to deny
titles as agents.
Recognising the imaginary can enable u s to begin t o develop titles that
perform in different ways, that is, connect particular people with particular
places in ways that better suit our worlds. In defending this claim I brie¯ y sketch
an alternative vision of pastoral land lease, one which is compatible with the
notion of joint native title and pastoralist lease land title. It is important to
recognise that at present this is no more than a thought experiment.
A joint title could try to represent Aboriginal land ownership within the
conceptual framework of Western land ownership. It could retain the notion of
empty space, trying to impose `Aboriginal boundaries’ on this space. These
boundaries could be taken as representing the limits of in¯ uence of `sacred sites
present within these boundaries. This leaves Kant’ s notion of a pr iori, empty and
undifferentiated space intact. It is in fact the route taken in the 1976 Northern
Territory Land Rights Legislation. By u sing this means of translation, areas of
Crown land can be declared as the freehold property of various Aboriginal clans.
250
RE-IMAGINING LAND OWNERSHIP IN AUSTRALIA
From the point of view of joint ownership between pastoralists an d Aborigi-
nes, however, this leaves us with the excruciating problem that the one area is
claimed by two opposed groups. Adjudication in favour of one or the other
seems the only possible way of settling the dispute. There is a further problem
in going this way. Native Title must be the basis of joint title negotiations,
because it is understood to have existed pr ior to any Western-style land titles in
Australia. Native Title of course can only be legitimately understood in the terms
of `the natives’ , and (on mai nland Australia) these terms do not include notions
of bounded area as a primary category in land ownership.
An alternative would be to follow the Aboriginal conceptual scheme of
understanding foci in the land as the basis of the meaningfulness of the land, and
hence as a basis for o wnership. To go this way we ® rst need to see that in a
pastoral lease not all places/lands are equivalent. Just as for the Aboriginal clans
who own t he land not all places/lands are equally and similarly important. We
can understand a pastoral r un as constituted by a hub siteÐ the homestead, the
machinery sheds, the yards and perhaps some home paddocks where the milking
cows are maintained. This is the site of primary signi® cance in a pastoral run and
might be understood by reference to Kant’ s live (ordered) island, or alternatively
by analogy to Aboriginal sacred sitesÐ those places where the ancestors lived,
doing things which constituted the site and its surrounds as meaningful.
In a sim ilar way that the o cean surrounding Kant s island becomes meaningful
as the island is enlivened, and that meaning ¯ ows from Aboriginal sacred sites
into the surrounds, the signi® cance of the pastoral lease hub site can be seen as
¯ owing into the surrounding land the tending and care of cattle and the lands
on which they thrive, ¯ ows from the hub.
33
With respect to these b roadlands,
what pastoralists need is the po ssibility of negotiating rights for harvesting these
broadlands (in the form of beef cattle) and this possi bility is co nstituted by the
care that exudes from the station. And then there are the outstations, the huts, the
bores with their pumps, the watering holes along r iver coursesÐ the subsidiary
sites. The use and maintenance of these sites too can be negotiated over. Claims
for use of these subsidiary sites can be seen as growing out of the caring.
This reading of meaningfulness in the l and as differentially signi® cant sites is
imminent in the life of a past oral run. What I have done hereÐ re-interpret
Kant’ s imagery and abandon the denial of the imaginary through which space is
constituted as a priori empt is a move which pastoralists could make. Going
this way pastoralists would ® nd they have signi® cant things to negotiate with
Aborigines. An d it is conceivable that agreements could be reached. Joint land
titles could enact these agreements.
I recognise that to make such a shift, to commit themselves to understanding
their pastoral leases and themselves in this way, would be no small thing for the
pastoralists. H owever it may be the only p ossibility for them to continue as
pastoralists. But for Aboriginal peoples too, to engage such a move by the
pastoralists would be politically dangerous. In this move sacred sites might seem
to be reduced in status. Such a move could be seen as compromising the
Aboriginal occupation of the high moral ground of spirituality, which they have
held to great advantage in the landrights debate in Australia. But for Aboriginal
groups, continuing with land title neutrally representing empty space might mean
251
HELEN VERRAN
that they regain use of their land at the expense of having t heir traditions of
knowing eclipsed by of® cial Australia yet again.
Making a reconceptualisation such as this the basis for n egotiation would
entail signi® cant changes in ontic and epistemic commitments by pastoralists,
`O cial Australia’ and Aboriginal Australia. To engage overtly in a politics of
ontic/epistemic commitments is clearly dangerous to both sides. On all sides this
is a more tricky enterprise than the covertly colonising politics we have come to
understand by deluding ourselves that we are moderns; a politics which overtly
centres around puri® cation and its essentialisms, all the time maintaining an
unacknowledged politics of coercion and insidious translation. Both these
politics are easier to do when they are kept separate. A politics of ontic/epistemic
commitments is a politics which has paradox at its centre.
34
Constituting our imaginaries as ontically and epistemically potent has brought
us a long way. In recognising this, I explicitly, although perhaps redundantly,
point out that imaginaries are not located in minds. The p astoral lease imaginary
I devised should n ot be taken as located in minds, not mine or pastoralists’ and
others’ who might take it up as useful. And neither should we take Kant’ s
imaginary of empty space as somehow lo cated in minds. Images and the stories
which people tell with their metaphors and causal connections mobilise these
imminent imaginaries and only in this indirect way contribute to constituting
them. If imaginaries are located anywhere, it is in the practices w hich constitute,
say, a pastoral run, or Aboriginal clan lands.
It is in the everyday messing around with mucky, obdurate stuff, and in the
conversations and other textsÐ o cial and unof® cialÐ that imaginaries are
enacted and enact. The imaginaries imminent in practices interpellate those
objects/subjects that/who are implicated in and by the practices, helping to
constitute them as objects/subjects. Owners, and lands, and titles, are co-pro-
duced as complex material-symbolic assemblages deeply implicated in and by
the others. We h ave come to understand knowing/acting in different ways.
Reading a pastoral lease as live places, an d incorporating this reading in land
title, recognises that the cattle run works the pastoralists as much as the
pastoralists work the run. Ti tles which are taken as enacting or performing
ownership focus attention on the materials, the actual places and practices. They
can be more easily understood as working in both directionsÐ mediating
between people and the landÐ compared to titles which are taken to represent
ownership of empty space. Titles, as heterogeneous assemblages accomplishing
particular translations in the long and complex connection between particular
people and particular sections of land, have agency, as much as owners and
lands, as complex hybrids, have agency. The problems that the pastoralists had
with Aborigines as k nowers and with non-human agency, the issues which
constituted the ® rst stumbling block at Coen in August 1994 in the negotiations
over joint title, are dissolved.
Titles have agency, but their agency is potent only in a community which has
a commitment to a shared, or a partially shared, imaginary. Bef ore they can
develop a joint title, pastoralists and Aborigines need to understand themselves
as an epistemic/o ntic community, to commit themselves to an imag inary, at least
partially shared, through which the land is mean ingful, and by which the primary
252
RE-IMAGINING LAND OWNERSHIP IN AUSTRALIA
categories of that meaningfulness are given. I have suggested a possibility which
entails the pastoralists and by implication `o cial Australia’ adopting a perfor-
mative epistemic mode and by doing so recognising the role and n ature of
ontic/epistemic imaginaries. Constituting such a joint title would amount to
of® cial recognition of land title as a monstrous hybrid. And it can only be
achieved by slowing down and reorienting.
Pastoralists and Aborigines, and Australians in general need courage, determi-
nation, and time to develop ourselves as at least a partially connecting knowing/
acting community, one which shares at least to some extent an ontic/epistemic
account of our land. We can no longer afford to delude ourselves that we are
moderns. Negotiations over working native title, pastoral leases and mining
leases together, will be constituted in, and turn will be constitutive of, a
community w hich accepts that it shares imaginaries and articulates those
imaginaries as part of recognising the myr iad hybrid assemblages with which we
constitute o ur worlds.
Notes
1
It is far from clear that governments formed by the Australian Labor Party would differ sign cantly from
their Liberal counterparts on this matter. It was a Labor government which in 1986 abandoned a celebrated
election promise of national, uniform land rights leg islation, and which before its removal from o ce had
already begun to formulate plans to amend the Native Title Act by curtailing the possibilities for negotiation
incorporated in the Act under pressure of getting endorsement of the legislation from representatives of
indigenous Australians.
2
I adopted the term `imaginary’ from Michele Le uff, The Philosophical Imaginary, The Atholone Press
Ltd, 1989. I use the notion in ways which have similarities to the ways Donna Haraway uses the term `trope’
in Modest Witness@Second M illenium. Female Man
Ó
Meets OncoMouse, New York: Routledge,
1997.
3
See R Horton, `African traditional thought and Western science’ , Africa, 37, 1967, pp 1±2; R Finnegan and
R Horton (eds) Modes of Thought, London: Faber, 1973; J Goody, The Domestication of the Savage Mind,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1977; B Wilson (ed), Rationality, Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 1977; M Hollis and S Lukes, Rationality and Relativism, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1982.
4
Feminists, symbolic interactionists, actor networ k theorists and those who see themselves practising
sociology of scienti® c knowledge have all embraced hetero geneity, though with somewhat different caveats.
5
Helen Watson-Verran and David Turnbull, `Science and other indigenous knowledge systems in Handbook
of Science and Technology Studies, S Jasanoff, G Markle, J Petersen and T Pinch (eds), London: Sage, 1995.
6
Bruno Latour, We Have Never Been Modern, trans Catherin Porter, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press, 1993, pp 11±12 .
7
Steven Shapin and Simon Schaffer, Leviathan and the Air Pump Hobbes Boyle, and the Experimental Life,
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1985; Steven Shapin, A Social History of Truth, Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1994.
8
Bruno Latour, op. cit., p 12.
9
My informant was a non-Aboriginal person working for the Cape York Land Council, a regional Aboriginal
organisation. The non-Aboriginal staff of this organisation act as an advisory team for Aboriginal negotiators
in meetings such as the Coen meeting, as well as in legal disputes.
10
The Yolngu community around Yirrkala in Arnhem Land in Australia’ s Northern Territory call me their
consultant philosopher. As a teacher of Yolngu tertiary students I was adopted into the Marika family in
1987. S ince then I have been deeply involved with the community as a member of a research group of
Aboriginal and non-Aboriginal Australians seeking to remake Yolngu schools in ways that better serve their
community.
11
Millpirrum and others Vs Nabalco Pty Ltd and the Common wealth of Australia, Melbourne: The Law Book
Co, 1971, p 143.
12
Ibid., p 271.
13
Ibid., p 272.
253
HELEN VERRAN
14
Helen Watson with the Yolngu Community at Yirrkala and D W Chambers, Singing the Land Signing the
Land, Geelong: Deakin University Press, 1989; Helen Watson-Verran and David Turnbull, `Science and other
indigenous knowledge systems’ , Handbook of Science and Technology Studies, London: Sage, 1995.
15
In particular pastoralists must be helped to reconsider truth as conventionally understood by Westerners:
`objective’ truth as corresponding to some prior reality. Some might understand this assertion as relativistismÐ
the view that truth is paradigm dependent, but the view that I am adopting differs from that `social realist’
position. I take the view that meaning is undecidable, and on this basis asser t that `objective’ truth (whether
it be a `relative’ truth or a `universal’ truth) must be considered as unattainable. This is to engage a notion
of knowledge which is not representationalist but which asserts that all knowledge derives from particular
practical contexts and is an embodiment rather than a representation. The idea that there is a `n atural world
for knowledge to be about, entirely distinct from the ways human and non-humans as knowers and/or agents
interact, must be abandoned.
16
In 1770, the year British of® cials claimed the `empty land of Australia as British, under the doctrine of terra
nullius, Kant took up a professorship in logic and metaphysi cs at the University of Konigsberg, a city deeply
caught up in European expansionism. He published the ® rst edition of his enormously in¯ uential work The
Critique of Pure Reason in 1781.
17
John Rundell, `Creativity and judgement: Kant on reaso n and imagination’ in Rundell and Robinson (eds)
Rethinking Imagination Culture and Creativity, London: Routledge, 1994, p 87.
18
Michele Le uff, The Philosophical Imaginary, London: The Atholone Press, 1989.
19
Ibid., pp 6.
20
Ibid., p 171.
21
Kant, Critique of Pure Reason. p 192.
22
Ibid., p 257.
23
John Rundell, op cit., p 95.
24
Le uff, op cit., p. 9.
25
The similarities and differences between Aboriginal groups in issues of land ownership are complex and
contested. The general similarity I am attributing here is merely that all Aboriginal groups own land through
a notion of what are called `sacred sites’ in English.
26
Helen Watson with the Yolngu community at Yirrkala and D W Chambers, op cit.
27
Helen Watson, `The politics of knowing and being known’ , Arena, 92, 1990, pp. 12140; Helen
Watson-Verran, `Contemporary Aboriginal life and some foundations in reasoning’ in Non-Formal Founda-
tions of Reason, W E Herfel and C A Hooker (eds), forthcoming.
28
This is an old and venerable controversy; one which Frege sought to end in his The Foundationsof Arithmetic
(Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 19 80) but one which caught up with him in the end. Murray Code suggests that
when Frege s program of showing that general concepts li ke qualities could be understood solely in terms
of precise systematic logic-mathematical propositionalfunctionsbegan to founder he lost interest in philosophy,
op cit., p 3.
29
David Turnbull gives a description of a similar sort of cognitive technology by which Micronesian navigators
maintain a dynamic map of the ocean. David Turnbull, Mapping the World in the Mind, Geelong: Deakin
University Press, 1991.
30
The invisibilityof this element of land titles is part of what Steven Shapin in A Social History of Truth (Chicago,
University of Chicago Press, 1994), ident es as epistemological decorum: the hiding of the practical
management of factual testimony in truth-making in action.
31
See David Turnbull, Maps are Territories, Chicago: University o f Chicago Press, 1993; `Remapping the
relationships between cartography, science and society , 1994.
32
In practice, of course, ontic and epistemic commitments are not separable, which is not to say that we should
not separate them for analytic purposes.
33
It can easily be seen that I have followed Aboriginal understandings both in reinterpreting Kant’ s imagery,
and in coming up with this picture of a pastoral lease title constituted as places which vary in signi® cance.
This reinterpretation of Kant produces a startling contrast. Kant fears the `watery chaos’ , which threatens
to overrun the fragile order of reason. Is this that fear, both of seduction and of insurrection, which is well
known to violent colonialists? In contrast the Aboriginal metaphor views the broadlands with an acceptance
of their `other’ state. Rather than fear, Aborigines metaphors evince an expectation, a hope that these unformed
stretches will be transformed by products of life at primary sites. Is this the hope o f a people `at home’ ?
34
And this possibly points to my projected role as a translator. We can understand arenas of politics over
ontic/epistemic commitments as constituting `passages’ in the sense that Kathryn Pyne Addelson is developing
the notion (Moral Passages, London:Routledge, 1994). In her terms `performative land title’ can be understood
as a sensitising concept, sensitising participants to new ways of seeing the past, and constituting an assemblage
through which a future with new catego ries is made. My participation as a translator in such a passage would
be characterised by working both with Aborigines and pastoralists, and perhaps also with miners, lawyers,
politicians etc in an arena of active negotiation. But my role is also in the academy, writing papers such as
this, where the sensitising concepts growing out of that work also do work. This sort of work I am doing
here is ontic/epistemic politics of a different kind; t he politics of developing theory.
254